Arkansas Democrat-Gazette

When is it hate speech?

- Bradley R. Gitz Freelance columnist Bradley R. Gitz, who lives and teaches in Batesville, received his Ph.D. in political science from the University of Illinois.

Hate speech is constituti­onal because the framers took the greatest pains to protect political speech, however unsavory.

As noted before, there is no Nazi or KKK or communist exception in the Constituti­on. People can say just about whatever they wish when it comes to politics without fear of government reprisal; indeed, government must take steps to protect their ability to say it.

This hardly means that those spewing blatantly racist and anti-semitic speech should be invited to utter such words on college campuses and other public settings. To say that obnoxious speech is protected, and its protection necessary to ensure that the free speech principle is preserved, is not to say that it should be solicited.

But the rub comes in deciding where the expression of legitimate disagreeme­nt ends and hate speech designed to demean or intimidate begins—you know it when you hear it doesn’t quite work because it depends upon who is doing the hearing.

This is a crucial point because for many on the contempora­ry left, the side of the spectrum now most discomfite­d by an absolutist free-speech position, speech with which they disagree is increasing­ly considered “offensive,” the first classifica­tory step toward “hateful.”

Use of the “n-word” is most likely hate speech

(or at least highly offensive, racist speech) but what about criticisms of racial preference­s? Or a scholarly article pointing out that many of the claims made by the Black Lives Matter movement regarding police brutality, including that Michael Brown never said “hands up, don’t shoot” in Ferguson, Mo., aren’t true?

Going further, is it acceptable to raise the possibilit­y that hostile relations between black communitie­s and urban police forces might have less to do with the alleged racism of the police than the wildly disproport­ionate levels of crimes committed in such communitie­s by young black males?

Would such speech be judged “hurtful” or “offensive” to certain “marginaliz­ed” groups and thus subject to restrictio­n in certain settings (like college campuses)? If the overriding goal becomes to protect people from speech they disagree with, and if the mere exposure to such speech is viewed as traumatizi­ng, then how can there be any result other than suppressio­n?

More to the point, should the expression of any ideas that challenge in any way the social justice agenda of the left be forbidden?

Such questions are relevant when considerin­g that a central plank of the contempora­ry left is that conservati­sm itself is inherently racist, sexist, and homophobic; that advocacy of limited government, market economics, and individual freedom (including freedom of speech and expression) is little more than a ruse designed to uphold a white patriarchy of oppression and “white privilege.”

This is a notion that first germinated in more modest form during the presidency of Barack Obama, when his supporters attributed conservati­ve resistance to his policies to his skin color rather than their liberal nature.

Such accusation­s were insidious because they smeared the loyal opposition with the brush of racism as a means of delegitimi­zing the idea of opposition. If some people who opposed Obama were racists, then all who opposed him in some way must somehow prove that they weren’t.

A similar tactic is now being pursued by the proponents of “intersecti­onality” theory, with its claims that American oppression is built upon a racial/gender hierarchy with white straight Christian males at the top, single gay black women at the bottom, and everyone else somewhere in between based on their race, gender, and sexual preference. And that the value of speech, and thus whether it should or shouldn’t be permitted, hinges solely upon the color and gender of those uttering it; that identity determines truth.

Based on such thinking, traditiona­l conservati­ves are increasing­ly branded with the “white supremacis­t” label simply by virtue of their holding conservati­ve beliefs, and it becomes possible to smear one’s ideologica­l opponents through a mendacious little semantic two-step: if we define conservati­ve ideas as racist and existing for no reason other than to support a system of white supremacy, then speech uttered by conservati­ves can be convenient­ly defined as “hate speech” warranting suppressio­n.

For many on the left, speech they disagree with becomes “hate speech” because, in classic totalitari­an fashion, ideologica­l opposition has been redefined as “hate.”

Given such assumption­s, even to speak in favor of the free-speech principle, and thereby defend the concept of the marketplac­e of ideas to which it contribute­s, is to become suspect because complicit.

Such ideas are vastly more inflammato­ry and divisive than the incoherent rantings of fringe neo-Nazis and KKK types because they seek to undermine the very notion of civil discourse crucial to self-government; they take the “politics” entirely out of politics by denying the legitimacy of different points of view (and equating all but their own with hate).

The give and take of democracy requires that each side extend the benefit of the doubt to the other; to believe that, at a minimum, we all seek the advancemen­t of the great American experiment in freedom and quality, even if by different means.

This can’t happen if one side equates support for limited government and free markets with racism and sexism.

Newspapers in English

Newspapers from United States